Friday, May 22, 2009

The State of the Intellectual Property Debate at LRC

I continue to do research for my book on intellectual property. It's a fascinating topic, and I don't think much insightful work has been done on the topic from a libertarian perspective since the brief comments on the topic by Murray Rothbard.

The advances that I believe I will be able to make on the topic will have to wait for the book. That said, I continue to be astonished at the direction Jeffery Tucker is attempting to take the debate.

In his most recent defense of what's your writing is my writing, he pulls out of the hat this gem, about a book owner who won't sell him rights to a book:

...he is clueless about the social value of the book
Social value? What the hell is social value? From an Austrian perspective there is no such thing. Here's Ludwig von Mises on the subject:

He who seeks to judge actions from the point of view of a pretended "social value," i.e., from the point of view of the "whole society," and to criticize them by comparison with the events in an imaginary socialist system in which his own will is supreme, has no use for economic calculation.
And, hey, it's Mises linking the term "social value" to a socialist system, not me, but it fits.

From there Tucker bitches that the book owner won't take the "market price":

... the "owner" of the IP – even though he is clueless about the social value of the book – cannot be persuaded to let it be published at a market price.
If an exchange is not conducted, how does Tucker no what the market price is?

Here's Mises again:

It is nonsensical to evaluate in money objects which are not negotiated on the market and to employ in calculations arbitrary items which do not refer to reality.
Again, the only "market price" is one where an exchange takes place. Tucker may call something else a market price (In this case, perhaps, two people who neither have the book to buy or sell would like to do a transaction), but it is clearly not the market price, since the owner is unwilling to sell at that price. The market price is where the owner is willing to sell. Does Tucker think the book owner wouldn't sell rights for, say, a billion dollars? I think Tucker is just underestimating the "market price" and bitching about some theoretical price which obviously doesn't fit the facts.

I hasten to add, for those who may raise the question, "What if the owner won't sell for a billion dollars?" Well, then the answer is simple, the owner values his book more than a billion dollars. However, I suspect that if Tucker offered the total stash tucked away at the Mises Institute, the owner would go for it.

On a happier note, I note that it appears that Lew Rockwell himself is backing away from the what's my writing is your writing madness. He recently turned against giving away at least some intellectual property, i.e., trade secrets and computer code:

Former federal prosecutor Bob Barr, the Libertarian presidential nominee last year, has joined Ralph Nader to call for...more federal intervention in the economy. Thanks, boys, we needed that.

That is, Messrs. Barr and Nader would use the federal cluster bomb to force car companies to reveal their trade secrets to every Tom, Dick,and Harry repair shop. This is called the "right to repair." Well, you certainly have the right to repair your own property, or other people's by contract, but not the right to steal the computer codes, etc. of Toyota in the name of "fair competition." That's always a synonym for the SWAT team.
Good points, Lew.

27 comments:

  1. I think there is an important distinction between what Tucker is speaking against, and what Rockwell is speaking against.

    In the former case, Tucker thinks that the "property" aspect of intellectual property is no such thing. That is, that publicly-available information cannot be owned. In the latter case, Rockwell is speaking against the idea that government should use force to compel private organizations to give away private information.

    These two positions are entirely reconcilable. If the manufacturers decided, ultimately, to make their repair codes etc. public, then that information could be copied by anyone. But if they don't make it public, the government has no business forcing them to do so.

    ReplyDelete
  2. @ Stewart

    Just when does something become "publicly available" in your world? The owner of the book Tucker is discussing is clearly not interested in the terms Tucker is offering. Yet somehow, in your world, Tucker has the right to usurp this owners rights and not those of the owner of manufacturing code?

    ReplyDelete
  3. Is there a title/release-date planned for the coming book? The intellectual property debate is raging here in Sweden, so it would be very interesting to read more on the topic ....

    ReplyDelete
  4. I should have more details on a release date, etc. in about a month.

    ReplyDelete
  5. @Robert, I don't think the distinction between what is public and what is private is actually that important here. I shouldn't have placed so much emphasis on those words in my earlier post.

    What's important for Rockwell's post is whether there is government coercion involved in forcing the dissemination of information. For Tucker's series of posts, the critical factor is whether government coercion is involved in preventing the dissemination of information.

    If a car manufacturer uses cryptography or secrecy to prevent others from accessing the car's electronic data, Rockwell's position is that the government should not force them to give the decryption keys away. Tucker's position is that, once those keys are known to the public (whether through reverse engineering, espionage, or the owner's manual), the car manufacturer has no basis for claiming ownership of that information. That also applies to the data which is later acquired using those decryption keys, such as internal programming data for the onboard computer.

    So these are two different arguments. Whether Rockwell and Tucker agree on them is unclear from the posts you linked to. I suspect that they do, given their respective roles at the LvMI, but it's not necessary that they do in order to reconcile the two positions, because they aren't mutually exclusive.

    ReplyDelete
  6. @ Stewart

    Let me make it simple. I write a one page analysis of the economy, I give it to you under the condition that you do not show it to anyone else, are you saying I have no righht to contract with you this way, that I must encrypt it?

    ReplyDelete
  7. If I sign that contract, and if I do show it to someone, then I've obviously violated our contract. To that extent, I think you're correct.

    In order to extend that logic to the contemporary system of copyrights, however, you have to believe that everyone is implicitly agreeing to contracts between themselves and the creators of every piece of original material that they encounter.

    Suppose that I do violate our contract, and I distribute your work to my colleagues. Even if we agree that I hold some moral culpability for that transgression, it's not at all clear that my colleagues have done anything wrong by accepting the paper from me. And if they continue to distribute it on their own, it's hard to see how they're violating any contract with you, since no such contract existed.

    Now, you may see that as being akin to accepting and reselling stolen goods. That presupposes that the information itself is your property, however. The contract alone cannot establish that.

    ReplyDelete
  8. It is actually possible - conceptually - to have something resembling current copyright in a libertarian social order: ISP companies, copy machine manufacturers, and others, can make a condition in their terms of use that copyright is to be respected, and that if anybody uses their technology to violate copyright, then they are liable to pay damages to the ISP or manufacturer. You could further make a condition of purchase that you shall only sell the copy machine if you agree to have the purchaser agree to these terms as well, and so forth.

    Even better, manufacturers of computers can make this a condition for the use of their product, and if you violate that provision, you will be taken to court under common contract law for violating the terms of your contract.

    There is nothing in libertarian theory that makes such conditional ownership transfer illegitimate.

    Of course, this leaves the possibilities of rival companies offering their products without such contracts... and let free competition take care of the argument.

    ReplyDelete
  9. @ James Rothfeld

    I absolutely agree.

    @James Rothfeld and @Stewart

    I do note that both of you are not specifically addressing the Tucker view, but if you check his writings,it is clear in his world that private contracts for intellectual creations would not be legitimate.

    In his world intellectually created works would not come with ownership rights, even if the creator will only release them under those terms! They are free for all to use, and some how not violate property rights.

    ReplyDelete
  10. The reason I do not address Tucker's argument is because it is probably one of the lousiest articles on the issue I have read in a long time. :)

    And I've no hesitation to rant and rail against the patent laws and argue till the cows come home that patent law as it exists now creates a) plain old rent-seeking, and b) creates waste by forcing people to invent around the patent law.

    Basic question about tucker's argument: does the noodle company KNOW how the noodle is designed? Because once it KNOWS it, there is no legitimate way to stop it from using this knowledge.

    So, while you the economist have a right to bind the person you gave your paper to a promise not to publish it, should this person LOSE the paper, and I find it, I can, of course, publish it - provided I am not in the process violating any contractual obligations I may have entered to otherwise (such as using a copy machine I bought under condition of NOT violating copyright)....

    ReplyDelete
  11. @Robert, if Tucker really does believe that individuals can't enter into voluntary contracts regarding their own behavior, then I agree with you entirely. That idea is ridiculous on its face.

    @James, your question about the noodles is essentially Tucker's point. It's only the temporary monopoly that the government grants patent-holders which prevents the company from making whatever kinds of noodles it likes.

    And your last paragraph captures my earlier point nicely: A contact can only (voluntarily) constrain the behavior of the parties who sign it. For everyone else, there is no constraint, and therefore no sense of intellectual ownership.

    ReplyDelete
  12. Tucker on rights to your own intellectual creations:

    If you have an idea, it is yours. You can do with it what you want. If you share it (sing, speak, broadcast, let others see the products of your ideas), others then have copies of it. They are entitled to do with their copies of the idea precisely what you can do with your idea. They can use it how they want provided they don't prevent others from doing with it what they want. This is a simple application of the non-aggression principle that governs a free society. Whether it is fashion, language, know how, or whatever, people are free to copy...What can you copy? Anything and everything. This is not "taking" anything from anyone. The original idea owner still has his. Other people now have their copies, and are free to improve it...You can even re-republish it under your own name, though that would amount to the socially repudiated vice of plagiarism (vice, not crime).

    http://tinyurl.com/qlayfr

    ReplyDelete
  13. I don't see an immediate contradiction between Tucker's position in the last article you quote, and mine - maybe only because it does NOT discuss the issue of what happens when I have a contract with the person I share my idea with not to copy it.

    I think that's the point about the book issue: if it is my book, and i gave it to you - the publisher - with the condition you not publish it without my consent, or that of my heirs, then you are bound to honor that commitment.

    no?

    ReplyDelete
  14. Robert, I think you may not fully understand Jeff Tucker's position. Nothing in that excerpt suggests that a person can't enter into a contract regarding intellectual creations. A constraint based on contracts is entirely different from a constraint based on a natural, default right to intellectual property.

    Suppose that I possess the only known copy of a never-published play by Shakespeare. I don't have any intellectual property rights over this play, but I nonetheless have complete control over its distribution, since I hold the only copy. As a condition of giving you a copy, suppose that I make you sign a contract saying that you will never redistribute it.

    I don't think that Jeff Tucker would have any problem with that contract. The excerpt you posted earlier is a description of what you, me, or anyone else can do with a Shakespearean play qua a Shakespearean play. Of course he isn't talking about the works of a long-dead author. But for Tucker, there is no difference (property-wise, anyway) between the intellectual works of Shakespeare, and the intellectual works of you or me. For most people, the informational content of the play cannot be owned due to its age, but for Tucker that content cannot be owned period.If you throw a contract into the scenario, it is no different. In my example above, you may very well be contractually prevented from redistributing the play, but you would not be under that constraint by default, or because of the nature of the play itself. With true intellectual property, the constraint is there even without your agreement, and it's that implicit constraint which Tucker argues against.

    ReplyDelete
  15. Oh drat.

    I need to qualify what I just wrote. Upon a closer reading, Jeff does seem to contradict my interpretation:

    "They can use it how they want provided they don't prevent others from doing with it what they want."If he means what you are implying he means, then I think you're right to criticize him. That statement is just silly.

    ReplyDelete
  16. @JamesRothfeld and @Stewart

    One problem with Tucker is that he is not a very precise writer. When he says you can copy anything, it is of course open to the clause, unless the original creator by contract prohibits such.

    Tucker in the passage I quote simply does not address this point clearly yeah or nay. However, I am quite sure that a full reading of Tucker's views on the topic would clearly show my interpretation of his meaning in the quote that he does not believe that you can have a contract based on the work of intellectual property. That's why he says you can copy anything.

    I quote Tucker from another piece:

    "But some may object that protecting IP is no different from protecting regular property. That is not so. Real property is scarce. The subjects of IP are not scarce, as Stephan Kinsella explains. Images, ideas, sounds, arrangements of letters on a page: these can be reproduced infinitely. For that reason, they can't be considered to be owned."

    http://tinyurl.com/23toxg

    ReplyDelete
  17. @JamesRothfeld and @Stewart

    Here's Tucker explaining Kinsella:

    "He made a strongly theoretical argument that ideas are not scarce, do not require rationing, are not diminished by their dissemination, and so cannot really be called property. All IP is unjust, he wrote. It is inconsistent with libertarian ethics and contrary to a free market. He favors the complete repeal of all intellectual-property laws."

    http://tinyurl.com/9px9gd

    Tucker again is not completely clear, but it is implied, if something can't be owned, you really can't have a contract about it.

    I really believe that Tucker would say you can't contract with regard to a book. May I suggest you email him and ask. I would do it myself, but he has advised me that he has blocked my emails, after I published, here at EPJ, examples of the vulgar language he sent to me in emails!

    ReplyDelete
  18. @Robert,

    Who gets the copyright/patent when two people invent something independently?

    Are thoughts alienable?

    ReplyDelete
  19. @Erick

    One of the problems with current IP thought is that it is generally viewed within a statist framework and there is further aggregation of IP protection than is appropriate.

    Are thoughts alienable?Absolutely.

    What is a consultant, if not a seller of thoughts?

    Who gets the copyright/patent when two people invent something independently?This question implies the aggregation trap which I am going to address in detail in my book.

    But, the short answer is they both do. If they both invent something independent and are not stealing from each other, then why shouldn't they both have the right to their creations?

    ReplyDelete
  20. Erick,

    we are not talking about a centrally administered state monopolisitic IP system, but about a common law system. If two people invent something at the same time, both have the right to use it, and to contract it out. Also, if somebody else figures out how do duplicate the invention simply by knowing about what it does, then that is fine, too.
    The idea as such is not protectable.
    Historic example: Mozart famously attended the performance of a piece of music that the author and owner had protected in so far that any copies of the music were not allowed to be duplicated, and that all performers were contractually obliged not to transcribe it. However, there was no contract that prohibited members of the audience to memorize it and then recreate it indepedently.

    http://www.classical.net/music/comp.lst/works/allegri/miserere.php

    So that's what Mozart did.

    Similar rules can be applied to cinemas: it may not be possible to prohibit the recording of a movie in principle, but it is possible for movie theaters to prohibit its patrons to record it. If anybody does, he would be guilty of violating the property rights of the cinema owner (analog to crying 'fire' in a theater not being illegal, but a property right violation).

    ReplyDelete
  21. I think Lawrence Lessig has staked out a "middle of the road" position on Copyright somewhere to the right of the "abolish all property in IP" position of some libertarians, and the corporatist statist machine that we have seen under DMCA, WIPO and the US government's, essentially protectionist, use of "free trade treaties" to extend it's IP regime around the world.

    Lessig's "copyleft" argument strikes me as the genuine "free market" / libertarian one, even though Lessig himself is something of a liberal (a.k.a. social democrat).

    More to the point, Lessig's defense of copyright shows that the founders of the American republic knew something about economics too. The following is a brief intro to Lessig's thinking, see here.

    ReplyDelete
  22. @Earth

    I am taking things in a completely different direction. See my most recent post:
    http://tinyurl.com/h7u6cs

    ReplyDelete
  23. Interesting discussion!

    Robert, this makes a lot of sense to me:

    If they both invent something independent and are not stealing from each other, then why shouldn't they both have the right to their creations?I am curious to see how you develop the idea in your forthcoming book!

    What is a consultant, if not a seller of thoughts?How does a consultant sell thoughts?

    The way I see it, a consultant sells his promise to appear in a certain place, at a certain time, in order to perform certain actions.

    I can see how my finger is alienable. I can cut it off and give it to you. I no longer have that finger. I cannot see how I can alienate my thoughts: I can always continue thinking whatever I want.

    Nor is there any guarantee that the person purchasing the person's time will gain any specific thinking process. At best there is a guarantee that he will feel certain feelings like "satisfaction".

    The closet thing that might come to this are SAT prep classes that guarantee a specific rise in test scores. But how do "your thinking will improve" and "you will have my thoughts" differ?

    @James,

    there was no contract that prohibited members of the audience to memorize it and then recreate it indepedentlySuppose there was, would it be valid?

    Can I sign a contract alienating rights to my brain?

    ReplyDelete
  24. Yes, it would have been valid, since it would be a contract regarding action, or restraint from action. "Alienation" has nothing to do with this. Free market copyright regulates not 'ideas' as such, but actions of individuals. Last time I checked, nobody ever argued that we cannot contractually agree to limit our actions - whether it is loud singing in the middle of the night, or looking after somebody kids. Not to copy or reproduce something is merely refraining from a specific type of action.
    If I gave you a million dollar under the condition that you never again sing in public, and you accepted this - would that be a valid contract?
    If I paid you a million dollar to not reveal a secret about me - would that not be a valid contract?
    How is this different from a contract that obliges you not to copy or reproduce something?
    At the same time, if two people invent something simultaneously, they are NOT bound contractually to any kind of action.
    What would, of course, be possible, is that you happen to work at a private university which stipulates in its contract with you that any invention you make must first be cleared with registry xyz for competing inventions. However, only people who directly or indirectly agreed to this system of clearance would be bound to it.
    Again, none of this has anything to do with deep discussions about whether ideas or not are properly 'property' - it's about human action, which any libertarian will agree can be regulated bindingly by contractual agreement.

    ReplyDelete
  25. What do you think about Rothbard's thoughts on the matter:

    Suppose that Smith makes the following agreement with the Jones Corporation: Smith, for the rest of his life, will obey all orders, under whatever conditions, that the Jones Corporation wishes to lay down. Now, in libertarian theory there is nothing to prevent Smith from making this agreement, and from serving the Jones Corporation and from obeying the latter’s orders indefinitely. The problem comes when, at some later date, Smith changes his mind and decides to leave. Shall he be held to his former voluntary promise? Our contention—and one that is fortunately upheld under present law—is that Smith’s promise was not a valid (i.e., not an enforceable) contract. There is no transfer of title in Smith’s agreement, because Smith’s control over his own body and will are inalienable. Since that control cannot be alienated, the agreement was not a valid contract, and therefore should not be enforceable. Smith’s agreement was a mere promise, which it might be held he is morally obligated to keep, but which should not be legally obligatoryShould we move the conversation to the new post?

    ReplyDelete
  26. @Erick

    Those are Rothbard's thoughts on signing your life away. For Rothbards thoughts on copyright go to man economy and state and you will see there are consistent with mine, although I advance it a step further with my recognition that all those who independently create something should hold copyright protection.

    ReplyDelete